The Three-Tier Corrective Reasoning
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.24234/wisdom.v7i2.133Keywords:
corrective reasoning/argumentation, science, scientific theories, truth, imagination, logical forms, conditions of validity, incorrect knowledgeAbstract
Written in honour of the late Academician Georg Brutian, the paper draws attention on one of the most special means of the transformative logic, the corrective argumentation, called here reasoning, that better emphasises the specific of arguments as such: that to inform semantically about the intention to arrive to certain conclusions. The corrective reasoning is that which reviews not only the validity of inferences, but also of the different types of premises lying at the basis of the theories people erect about every moment and aspect of life and reality. The corrective reasoning is the form of the capacity to critique the former judgements and has three tiers: the first – concluding that the former/existing theory was proven to be wrong; the second – gathering the arguments of alternative theories, and the third – focusing on the best/or even only in present the more economical alternative theory.
Every tier has more strata of reasoning whose result is the correction: the conclusion that 1) the old results (and focus on examples/situations), so the old theories require/directly send to their refutation, and 2) the conclusion suggests just some arguments of alternative theories. The corrective argumentation is not reduced to propositions, neither to syllogisms, but is constituted of the many relationships between statements.
From all the domains the corrective argumentation does manifest within and about, the scientific one was chose just because here the corrective approach is compulsory and its pattern – the most obvious. An epistemological analysis was deployed and it was demonstrated that the goal of the corrective reasoning is truth (in a certain concrete temporal interval) and the way to it involves the better understanding of the semantic level of language and its dependence on the real world.
Because the corrective reasoning is a question of daring and imagining new theories, the mechanism of this process was sketched by showing that consciousness has not only a passive face (that of representations) but always an active one too (the intention toward the external world), and by focusing on the logical forms as structures of thinking and their relationships with the external world “through the medium of” their internal consistence and coherence. In its turn, argumentation has in view both the formal model and substantial model of situations.
The specific of the corrective reasoning in science shows the difficulty of this endeavour and some deviations from this specific. The conclusion is that, indeed, the corrective reasoning is revolutionary.
Downloads
References
Anscombre, J.-C., & Ducrot, O. (1976). L'argumentation dans la langue. Langages, 10(42), 5-27.
Anscombre, J.-C., & Ducrot, O. (1983). L’argumentation dans la langue. Bruxelles : Pierre Mardaga éditeur.
Aristotle. (2000). Nicomachean Ethics. (R. Crisps, Ed., & Trans.) Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 150a12-13.
Bastit, M. (2016). La science aristotélicienne des animaux et la biologie contemporaine: d’ Empédocle et Démocrite à Aristote. Noema, XV, 195-214.
Bazac, A. (2008). Sur l'imagination chez Merleau-Ponty et Bachelard. Analele Universit??ii din Craiova, Seria Filosofie, nr. 22 (2), 19-48.
Bazac, A. (2016). The regret. Egophobia, 46, 14 June 2016,
http://egophobia.ro/?p=11243.
Brutian, G. (1998). Logic, Language and Argumentation in Projection of Philosophical Knowledge. Armenian Library of Calouste Gulbenkian Foundation. Lisbon: Printed by Grafica De Coimbra, Ltd.
Carettini, G.P. (1988). Peirce, Holmes, Popper. In E. Umberto, & T. Sebeok (Ed.) (1983) The Sign of Three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce (pp. 135-153). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Chen X. (2015). The Emergence and Development of Causal Representations. In L. Magnani et al. Philosophy and Cognitive Science II, Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics. Switzerland: Springer International Publishing, 21-34.
Delbrück, M. (1971). Aristotle-totle-totle” in “0f Microbes and Life. (J. Monod, & E. Borek, Eds.) New York: Columbia University Press, 50-55.
Deux fabulistes arméniens du Moyen Âge: Mkhithar Goch, Vardan Ayguéktsi, À la mémoire des arménistes français Jean Saint-Martin (1731-1832) et Frédéric Macler (1869-1938), Rédacteur Gohar Grigorian, Erévan: Éditions Nahapet.
Di Vita, N. (2016). Il logos tra filosofia e vita. Una nota sullo stroicismo antico. Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology and Practical Philosophy, Vol. VIII, June, 121-142.
Dumitru, M. (2015). Logical Form. In C?t?lin Vasilescu, Maria-Luisa Flonta, Ioana Cr?ciun (Eds.) On Form and Pattern (pp. 11-16). Bucure?ti: Editura Academiei Române.
Eklund, A., Nichols, T.E., & Knutsson, H. (2016). Cluster failure: Why fMRI inferences for spatial extent have inflated false-positive rates. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 113(28).
DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1602413113.
Eco, U. (1988). Horns, Hooves, Insteps: Some Hypotheses on Three Types of Abduction. In E. Umberto, & T.A. Sebeok (Eds.) (1983), The Sign of Three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce (198-220). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Fine, K. (1994). Essence and Modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1-16.
Fine, K. (1989). The Problem of De Re Modality. In J. Almog, J. Perry, H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (197-272). New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press (reprinted in Modality and Tense: Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press 2005).
Fine, K. (2005). The Varieties of Necessity. In Modality and Tense: Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press. http://philosophy.fas.nyu.edu/object/kitfine.
Grcic, J. (2008). The Halo Effect Fallacy. E-Logos, Electronic Journal for Philosophy, 1-6.
Hempel, C.G. (1965). The Logic of Functional Analysis. In Hempel, (1959) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 297-330), New York: The Free Press; London: Collier-Macmillan Lmd.
Morris, Ch.W. (1938). Foundations of the Theory of Signs. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, I(2). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Nadin, M. (2015). Anticipation and Creation. In Libertas Mathematica (new series), 35(2), 1-16.
Peirce, Ch.S. (1932). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. (Ch. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, & A.W. Burks, Eds.), Vol. 2, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, Ch.S. (1958). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. (A.W. Burks, Ed.), Vol. 7, Cam-bridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Popper, K. (1994). The Myth of the Framework: In defence of Science and Rationality, (1965; 1986). (M.A. Notturno, Ed.), Abingdon, New York: Routledge.
Reichertz, J. (2010). Abduction: The Logic of Discovery of Grounded Theory. FQS Forum: Qualitative Social Research/Sozialforschung, 11(1), Art. 13.
Russell, B. (1950). An Outline of Intellectual Rubbish. In Russell, Unpopular Essays (pp. 71-111), New York: Simon & Schuster.
Sartre, J.-P. (1936). L’imagination, Paris: F. Alcan.
Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge, Massachussets, London: MIT Press.
Toulmin, S.E. (2003). The Uses of Argument (1958). Updated Edition, Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Toulmin, S.E. (1977). Human Understanding: The Collective Use and Evolution of Concepts. (1972), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Creative Commons Attribution-Non-Commercial (CC BY-NC). CC BY-NC allows users to copy and distribute the article, provided this is not done for commercial purposes. The users may adapt – remix, transform, and build upon the material giving appropriate credit, and providing a link to the license. The full details of the license are available at https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/.